The most consequential book I read as a US History grad student
Morton Horwitz's Transformation of American Law
Part of this blog (maybe one day it will be a dedicated section) is designed to be a place where I review things I’ve read that I think are noteworthy. I’m going to begin that with one of the most influential books I read as a grad student, Morton J. Horwitz’s The Transformation of American Law, 1780-1860, published in 1977. I believe this is still a very important text for students of legal history, but unfortunately I don’t think it’s widely read outside that small sub-discipline, in spite of winning a Bancroft. That’s unfortunate.
Horwitz argued a fairly radical point, which I think never received wide enough recognition due to the subject matter and his extremely difficult (dense and dry) style. He said, “I seek to show that one of the crucial choices made during the antebellum period was to promote economic growth primarily through the legal, not the tax, system, a choice which had major consequences for the distribution of wealth and power in American society” (xv). He also had some interesting ideas about the way “the internal technical life of a field generates autonomous forces that determine its history” (xi). We make a mistake, Horwitz believed, if we fail to account for the activities and interests of lawyers, judges, the legal profession, law schools, and other interested parties when looking at how “the law” influenced history. The same could probably be said, with equally interesting results, for religion, medicine, or the study of history itself.
Horwitz focused on common law rather than on landmark Supreme Court decisions. Constitutional law, he said, “represents episodic legal intervention buttressed by a rhetorical tradition that is often an unreliable guide to the slower (and often more unconscious) processes of legal change in America” (xii). Constitutional law also focuses our attention on judicial review, rather than what Horwitz characterized as a very active, constructive, legislative role taken on by nineteenth century jurists. “By 1820,” he said, “the process of common law decision making had taken on many of the qualities of legislation. As judges began to conceive of common law adjudication as a process of making and not merely discovering legal rules, they were led to frame general doctrines based on a self-conscious consideration of social and economic policies” (2). The ancient belief in “an eternal set of principles expressed in custom and derived from natural law” inherited from European tradition gave way to an understanding of law as “an instrument of policy” that could be used “for governing society and promoting socially desirable conduct” (30). Once this change had been made, the game became one of defining the terms “socially desirable.”
The major examples Horwitz used to illustrate this change surround the competing uses for water, such as mill power, irrigation, navigation, and fishing (his grad student Ted Steinberg wrote the definitive environmental history of the New England textile industry, Nature, Incorporated). Controversies around water illustrated the problems inherent in “a conception of ownership [including] a commitment to absolute dominion” (31). There was a problem, in a newly-settled land, respecting the concept that “first in time is first in right” (32). While it made sense to grant initial exclusivity to a developer (how many grist mills did a new town need?), “can the claims of still greater efficiency through competition be denied?” Horwitz asked (34). But the real issue was not the particular decisions made, but the way the decisions were made.
Horwitz’s point was that “By changing the rules and disguising the changes in the complexities of technical legal doctrine, the facade of economic security can be maintained even as new property is allowed to sweep away the old” (34). The legal system, Horwitz argued, was used to not only change the rules of the game to benefit an increasingly elite class, but also to hide the fact that these changes were being made. This is a great argument. What it needs is some people in the story to show how it happened and how people reacted, assuming anyone on the short end of the transaction knew it was happening.
This raises an interesting question: how do we tell stories about things we now see were happening, but that people of the time were unaware of, either because the evidence was hidden, or they just didn’t see things the way we do? Especially when people knew something was wrong, but couldn’t quite put their finger on it -- or blamed it on the wrong thing? The story isn’t just about unintended consequences, it’s about misunderstood consequences.
But back to Horwitz, who said an 1844 Massachusetts decision in Cary v. Daniels was “premised on the desirability of maximizing economic development even at the cost of equal distribution” (41). The court’s preference of profit over equity opened the door for other courts to direct business toward their idea of the public good and “enabled common law judges to choose the direction of American economic development,” at least when it came into contact with older legal ideas of property and equity (42). I’ve been wondering how people at the time responded to these changes; maybe one place to look would be at the “storm of bitter protest” caused by the “extension of the mill act to manufacturing establishments” (51). Apparently there were people who saw through the courts’ gambit and argued that while early mills had been almost communal in nature, “manufacturing establishments were private institutions” (51). Citizens rejected the law’s provisions for relief, arguing “Generally, the mills and mill seats are in the hands of the active and wealthy -- able to make the sufferers repent, if they resort to the law” (52).
One of the state’s main economic development tools was eminent domain. But tied up with it was the idea of chartered monopoly and of limited liability. A State grant was no good, in the minds of 19th-century businessmen, if “the grantee cannot exercise it without being subject to ruinous damages, so as to swell the cost of their enterprise” beyond its ability to make a profit, one commentator warned (69). Rather than examining whether these social costs really argued against the business going forward (especially in the cases of railroads in the 1840s-60s), Horwitz says the courts socialized “consequential damages.” This enabled the courts to disqualify them, under the legal justification that “The law gives no private remedy for anything but a private wrong” (quoting the standard legal text, Blackstone, 76). So the costs were socialized (in economic terms, externalized) at the same time the benefits were privatized in the form of corporate profits.
Over the course of the nineteenth century, Horwitz said the basic “attitude toward legal liability” became “based on the assumption that the ‘quiet citizen must keep out of the way of the exuberantly active one.’ Indeed, the law of negligence became a leading means by which the dynamic and growing forces in American society were able to challenge and eventually overwhelm the weak...After 1840 the principal that one could not be held liable for socially useful activity exercised with due care became a commonplace in American law” (99). The effect of this change was “to create immunities from legal liability and thereby to provide substantial subsidies” to developers (100). “Change brought about through technical legal doctrine,” Horwitz said, “can more easily disguise underlying political choices [than] Subsidy through the tax system” (101). Horwitz said “there is reason to suppose” that this “was not simply an abstract effort to avoid political contention but that it entailed more conscious decisions about who would bear the burdens of economic growth.” This is a really interesting claim, but it needs to be backed up, I think, with some evidence that actual people made this decision at the time. Like with quotes from the actual people, if they could be found.
“In every state after 1790,” Horwitz said, “a political decision to avoid promoting economic growth primarily through taxing seems to have crystallized” (109). Shays’ and the Whiskey Rebellions would have helped that crystalization, as well as recognition that there wasn’t any money out there to get through taxing. Horwitz continued, “By 1800 a pattern of private ownership of banks, insurance companies, and transportation facilities had become dominant in America” (110). Again, true, but the question is why? Attributing the change in definition of corporations to an individualist spirit seems to put the cart before the horse, since early corporations “continued to argue both that their charters were grants of exclusive property interests and that economic rivalry was, in effect, a private law nuisance to property” (114). This seems like a blatantly opportunistic attempt to have your cake and eat it to: the corporations were capitalizing on their status as something in between public and private, with the benefits of both. But the question remains, how did corporations get from the 18th-century definition of a public body (like a municipality) working for the public good, to the 19th-century definition of a private company doing business to produce profit for its investors?
Horwitz said “eighteenth century...contract law was essentially antagonistic to the interests of commercial classes,” because it sought to judge the underlying fairness or justice of the exchange in question (167). But ironically, the argument for judging contracts objectively on their terms was based on a claim that value was subjective and circumstantial. Promissory notes were used in place of cash, and “in order to make notes negotiable a subsequent endorsee [must] be allowed to recover on the note regardless of the consideration between the original parties” (177). The same-as-cash nature of the note that made it effective as currency enabled “merchants to exclude the question of the equality of a bargain by transacting their business through promissory notes,” and excluded the courts from playing a role in judging the fairness of a transaction. The contract became an authority unto itself and was no longer seen as part of a tradition of dealings based on just prices or practices. (This is a missing link in the market transition story -- many historians assume the change required a move to a cash-based, spot market. Horwitz showed the market could be depersonalized and objectified even before it stopped being based on long-term, credit relationships.)
Contract law changed the laborers’ world, Horwitz said, through the “doctrine of ‘assumption of risk,’ [in which] contract ideology...emasculated all prior conceptions of substantive justice.” The fiction of “equal bargaining power inevitably became established as the inarticulate major premise of all legal and economic analysis. The circle was completed: the law had come simply to ratify those forms of inequality that the market system produced” (210).
Returning to the issue of negotiable notes, Horwitz pointed out that common law not only established rules allowing “subsequent innocent purchasers” to collect on the notes regardless of any defects in the original deal, but it allowed “the legal system [to] sanction private arrangements whose effect was to increase the supply of money by allowing individuals to agree to substitute their own notes for currency designated by the state” (211). This has interesting implications for the pace and distribution of economic development. After Andrew Jackson’s specie circular, for example, currency was in short supply in already-settled areas because people carried it out to the land offices to buy parcels in Michigan and Indiana. Growth would have been much slower, and demand for state money creation would have been more urgent, if people like the upstate New York merchants I studied for Peppermint Kings had not been able to do business using notes. But I wonder, how much was “the law” making policy? Couldn’t it also be argued that these people were making policy, and “the law” was just trying to keep up with them? Who actually had the agency -- who was in the driver’s seat -- seems to be a major unanswered question here. Massachusetts Chief Justice Theophilus Parsons’ 1808 remarks seem the suggest the law was following: “The circulation of negotiable paper,” he said, “is extremely useful to trade, as it multiplies commercial credit, and the notes pass form man to man as cash. Any rule of law, tending unnecessarily to suppress this circulation, is therefore against public policy” (220).
Horwitz concluded his book by describing the “rise of legal formalism” in the 1840s and 50s. “If a flexible, instrumental conception of law was necessary” to promote economic development, he said, “it was no longer needed once the major beneficiaries...had obtained the bulk of their objectives” (254). In fact, just the opposite. The law needed to become (and be seen as) “self-contained, apolitical, and inexorable;” built on scientific logic and practiced by professionals. Having used it to get to power, Horwitz said, the ruling class used legal formalism as a way of “disguising and suppressing the inevitably political and redistributive functions of law” (266). This is a startling conclusion, especially if one came to this book thinking the law was actually ever apolitical or objective. From a broader context, Horwitz showed that American law in the nineteenth century was no different in this respect from that of any other time or place. He outlined some of the ways an emerging elite used and changed the law to facilitate its rise, although he unfortunately left the names and faces out of the story. Horwitz believed recent historians had been “more concerned with finding evidence of governmental intervention than they were in asking in whose interest these regulations were forged” (xiv). His book suggests who some of the targets of questions should be -- it remains to be seen whether it can be proved these people were acting consciously, and how they and society at large understood their actions and the changes that resulted.
The reason I found this the most consequential book in my US field reading list was that this wasn’t a revisionist counter-history by some firebrand radical like Howard Zinn. It was a legal history by a Harvard professor. And it still exploded my brain.